Language Evolution
April 25, 2000
Everybody read:
Smith, J.M. and E. Smathmary. 1995. Chapter 17: The evolution of language. In
The major transitions in evolution. New York: W.H. Freeman and Co.: 281-309.
(An entertaining, easy read)
OR
Pinker, S. 1997. Evolutionary biology and the evolution of language. In M. Gopnik
(ed.) The inheritance and innateness of grammars. New York: Oxford University
Press: 181-208. (A very good background on the different views of the evolution of
language…a little denser than Smith and Smathmary)
Theories of language evolution
Pinker, S. and P. Bloom. 1990. Natural language and natural selection. Behavioral
and Brain Sciences 13(4): 707-784.
Many people have argued that the evolution of the human language faculty cannot be
explained by Darwinian natural selection. Chomsky and Gould have suggested that language
may have evolved as the by-product of selection for other abilities or as a consequence
of as-yet unknown laws of growth and form. Others have argued that a biological specialization
for grammar is incompatible with every tenet of Darwinian theory -- that it shows
no genetic variation, could not exist in any intermediate forms, confers no selective
advantage, and would require more evolutionary time and genomic space than is available.
We examine these arguments and show that they depend on inaccurate assumptions about
biology or language or both. Evolutionary theory offers clear criteria for when a
trait should be attributed to natural selection: complex design for some function,
and the absence of alternative processes capable of explaining such complexity. Human
language meets this criterion: grammar is a complex mechanism tailored to the transmission
of propositional structures through a serial interface. Autonomous and arbitrary
grammatical phenomena have been offered as counterexamples to the position that language
is an adaptation, but this reasoning is unsound: communication protocols depend on
arbitrary conventions that are adaptive as long as they are shared. Consequently,
language acquisition in the child should systematically differ from language evolution
in the species and attempts to analogize them are misleading. Reviewing other arguments
and data, we conclude that there is every reason to believe that a specialization
for grammar evolved by a conventional neo-Darwinian process.
Botha, Rudolf P. 2000. Discussing the evolution of the assorted beasts called
language. Language & Communication 20(2): 149-161.
Evaluates research on language evolution in relation to their compliance with the
condition of ontological transparency. Different ontological characterizations of
the concept of language; Analysis of language structure and the existing disconnected,
inconclusive discussions of specific questions of language evolution.
Ganger, J. and K. Stromswold. 1998. Innateness,
evolution, and genetics of language. Human Biology 70(2): 199-213.
Our goal in this article is to review a debate over the evolution of language and
to suggest some keys to its resolution. We begin with a review of some of the theoretical
and empirical evidence for the innateness of language that has caused renewed interest
in the evolution of language. In a second section we review some prominent theories
of the evolution of language, focusing on the controversy over whether language could
have been adapted for some purpose. We argue that for evolutionary studies of language
to advance, theorists must make more persuasive arguments for the purpose of language,
and, furthermore, linguists must continue to develop a detailed theory of syntax.
Finally, we suggest ways that behavioral and population genetics could help to inform
studies of the evolution of language.
Lieberman, P. 1990. The evolution of human language. Seminars in Speech and Language
11(2): 63-76.
Nowak, M.A., J.B. Plotkin, and V.A.A. Jansen.
The evolution of syntactic communication. Nature 404: 495-498.
Aiello, Leslie C. 1996. Terrestriality, bipedalism and the origin of language.
In Runciman, W.G., J.M. Smith and R.I.M. Dunbar (eds.) Proceedings of the British
Academy, 88; Evolution of social behavior patterns in primates and man. London:
Oxford University Press: 269-289.
Language is unique to humans, but in the context of the long time span of human evolution
it is a fairly recent innovation. All evidence suggests that human brain size and
inferred cognitive and linguistic abilities reached their modern norms only within
the last quarter of a million years. Foundations for human linguistic and cognitive
evolution, however, lie much further back in evolutionary history. Arguments are
presented suggesting that these unique human abilities are the legacy of our ancestors'
terrestrial and bipedal adaptations. Both terrestriality and bipedalism are directly
associated with the unique human propensity for vocal communication, including the
range and quality of sound that all humans are capable of producing. Furthermore,
terrestriality and bipedalism can also be directly associated with brain size and
cognition. Increases in group size accompanying a committed terrestrial adaptation
would have put a premium on social, or Machiavellian intelligence while bipedalism
would have been associated with the increased neural circuitry involved in enhanced
speed and co-ordination of hand and arm movements. The constricted bipedal pelvis
would have also necessitated the birth of less mature offspring, exposing them to
a rich environment while the brain was still rapidly growing and developing. A larger
brain is not without its costs, however. Energetic arguments are also presented which
suggest that a large brain can only evolve in concert with a change to a high quality
diet, resulting directly in lifestyle changes for our early ancestors. All of the
features were in place by the appearance of early Homo erectus about 1.8 million
years ago and underpinned an apparently stable hominine adaptation that lasted for
well over 1.5 million years. Modern human cognitive and linguistic talents are rooted
in this earlier Homo erectus adaptation and may have begun to develop in response
to further need for increased group size. Both the costs and the benefits of this
later increase in brain size are considered.
Transition
Nowak, M.A., D.C. Krakauer, and A. Dress.
1999. An error limit for the evolution of language. Proceedings of the Royal Society
Biological Sciences Series B 266(1433): 2131-2136.
On the evolutionary trajectory that led to human language there must have been a
transition from a fairly limited to an essentially unlimited communication system.
The structure of modern human languages reveals at least two steps that are required
for such a transition: in all languages (i) a small number of phonemes are used to
generate a large number of words; and (ii) a large number of words are used to a
produce an unlimited number of sentences. The first (and simpler) step is the topic
of the current paper. We study the evolution of communication in the presence of
errors and show that this limits the number of objects (or concepts) that can be
described by a simple communication system. The evolutionary optimum is achieved
by using only a small number of signals to describe a few valuable concepts. Adding
more signals does not increase the fitness of a language. This represents an error
limit for the evolution of communication. We show that this error limit can be overcome
by combining signals (phonemes) into words. The transition from an analogue to a
digital system was a necessary step toward the evolution of human language.
Ujhelyi, M. 1996. Is there any intermediate stage between animal communication
and language? Journal of Theoretical Biology 180(1): 71-76.
Animal communication and human language have fundamental differences in their structures
and functions. Furthermore, there is no living species demonstrating an intermediate
stage of language evolution. Thus, we have difficulty in finding characteristics
attributable to a communication system which can already be considered as a starting
point for linguistic evolution. However, some findings coming from neurolinguistic
research give us the opportunity to suppose that varying and arranging linguistic
elements can be detached from other grammatical functions. Further information in
this direction comes from apes' language-teaching experiments; namely bonobos (Pan
paniscus) are able to understand and produce differences in meaning by varying word
arrangements. Based on these results one can suppose that an acoustic signal system,
which possesses discrete units for variable use, might be very ancient and might
exist independent and prior to a more advanced language state. In the natural setting,
acoustic territorial marking behaviour is exposed to selection pressure to elaborate
sign systems built up from discrete, variable units. In addition to the well-known
territorial bird songs, some monkey species and all species of lesser apes have territorial
songs fitting these criteria. The analyses of the so-called long calls in chimpanzees
and bonobos make it likely that the group-living great apes preserved the ability
to create syntactically different calls, which would be developed by requirements
of social life. A call repertoire emerged in these species, which contained a large
number of call variants at group level available for each group member via social
learning. This type of animal call is different from ordinary animal communication;
it shows some features of human language. It can represent an intermediate stage
between animal communication and language, and communication systems similar to this
one can be considered as a starting point or first stage of language evolution.
Ujhelyi, M. 1998. Long-call structure in apes
as a possible precursor to language. In Hurford, J.R., M. Studdert-Kennedy, and C.
Knight (eds.) Approaches to the evolution of language. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press: 177-189.
Locke, J. J. 1998. Social sound-making as a precursor to spoken language. In Hurtford,
J.R., M. Studdert-Kennedy, and C. Knight (eds.) Approaches to the evolution of
language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press: 190-201.
Bickerton, D. 1998. Catastrophic evolution: the case for a single step from protolanguage
to full human language. In Hurtford, J.R., M. Studdert-Kennedy, and C. Knight (eds.)
Approaches to the evolution of language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press:
341-358.
Corballis, M. 1999. The gestural origins of
language. American Scientist 87(2).
Human language is one of the finest accomplishments of biological evolution. Much
of our species’ success is fundamentally dependent on the capacity of language to
generate ideas that allow us to escape from the immediate present or to describe
events and phenomena that have never existed. Yet the origin and evolution of this
powerful tool is quite mysterious. Other forms of animal communication bear so little
resemblance to human language that it seems unlikely that any of them could be a
precursor to spoken language. Pulling together various observations on the neurology
of language, the sophistication and cross-cultural nature of sign languages, and
the ability of apes to communicate with signs, Corballis argues that the origins
of human language may lie in manual gestures, not in vocalization.
Arbib, M.A. and G. Rizzolatti. 1997. Neural expectations: A possible evolutionary
path from manual skills to language. Communication and Cognition 29: 393-424.
Games and models
Nowak, M.A. and D.C. Krakauer. 1999. The
evolution of language. PNAS 96(14): 8028-8033.
The emergence of language was a defining moment in the evolution of modern humans.
It was an innovation that changed radically the character of human society. Here,
we provide an approach to language evolution based on evolutionary game theory. We
explore the ways in which protolanguages can evolve in a nonlinguistic society and
how specific signals can become associated with specific objects. We assume that
early in the evolution of language, errors in signaling and perception would be common.
We model the probability of misunderstanding a signal and show that this limits the
number of objects that can be described by a protolanguage. This "error limit"
is not overcome by employing more sounds but by combining a small set of more easily
distinguishable sounds into words. The process of "word formation" enables
a language to encode an essentially unlimited number of objects. Next, we analyze
how words can be combined into sentences and specify the conditions for the evolution
of very simple grammatical rules. We argue that grammar originated as a simplified
rule system that evolved by natural selection to reduce mistakes in communication.
Our theory provides a systematic approach for thinking about the origin and evolution
of human language.
Nowak, M.A., J.B. Plotkin, and D.C. Krakauer. 1999. The evolutionary language
game. Journal of Theoretical Biology 200(2): 147-162.
We explore how evolutionary game dynamics have to be modified to accommodate a mathematical
framework for the evolution of language. In particular, we are interested in the
evolution of vocabulary, that is associations between signals and objects. We assume
that successful communication contributes to biological fitness: individuals who
communicate well leave more offspring. Children inherit from their parents a strategy
for language learning (a language acquisition device). We consider three mechanisms
whereby language is passed from one generation to the next: (i) parental learning:
children learn the language of their parents; (ii) role model learning: children
learn the language of individuals with a high payoff; and (iii) random learning:
children learn the language of randomly chosen individuals. We show that parental
and role model learning outperform random learning. Then we introduce mistakes in
language learning and study how this process changes language over time. Mistakes
increase the overall efficacy of parental and role model learning: in a world with
errors evolutionary adaptation is more efficient. Our model also provides a simple
explanation why homonomy is common while synonymy is rare.
Warneryd, K. 1995. Language, evolution, and the theory of games. In Casti, J.L.
and A Karlqvist (eds.) Cooperation and conflict in general evolutionary processes.
New York: John Wiley and sons: 405-421.
Hurford, J.R. 1991. The evolution of the critical period for language acquisition.
Cognition 40(3): 159-202.
Evidence suggests that there is a critical, or at least a sensitive, period for language
acquisition, which ends around puberty. The existence of this period is explained
by an evolutionary model which assumes that (a) linguistic ability is in principle
(if not in practice) measurable, and (b) the amount of language controlled by an
individual conferred selective advantage on it. In this model, the language faculty
is seen as adaptive, favoured by natural selection, while the critical period for
language acquisition itself is not an adaptation, but arises from the interplay of
genetic factors influencing life-history characters in relation to language acquisition.
The evolutionary model is implemented on a computer and simulations of populations
evolving under various plausible, if idealized, conditions result in clear critical
period effects, which end around puberty.
Related works for additional reading
Gibson, K.R. and T. Ingold (eds.) 1993. Tools, language and cognition in human
evolution. Cambridge: Cambridge university press.
Hornstein, N. 1996. From icons to symbols: some speculations on the origins of
language. In Brandon, R. N. (author) Cambridge studies in philosophy and biology;
concepts and methods of evolutionary biology. Cambridge: Cambridge university
press: 85-105.
Haldane, J.B.S. 1992. Animal communication and the origin of human language (reprint).
Current science (Bangalore) 63(9): 604-611.
Lieberman, P. 1984. The biology and evolution of language. Cambridge, Mass.:
Harvard University Press.
Lieberman, P. 1991. Uniquely human: the evolution of speech, thought, and selfless
behavior. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
Lieberman, P. 1998. Eve spoke: human language and human evolution. New
York: W.W. Norton.